Apr 18, 2006
Anarchy in Prague
[cross-posted at Austro-Athenian Empire]
Tomorrow I leave for the Prague Conference on Political Economy. This wont be the farthest east Ive gone in Europe, since Vietri sul Mare, on the west coast of Italy just south of Naples, is actually further east. (One of those things you dont believe until you look at a map like the fact that Reno, Nevada, is west of Los Angeles.) But itll be the farthest inland Ive been in Europe, as well as my first visit to a former communist country.
The topic of my presentation is Rule-following, Praxeology, and Anarchy. Heres an abstract:
Tomorrow I leave for the Prague Conference on Political Economy. This wont be the farthest east Ive gone in Europe, since Vietri sul Mare, on the west coast of Italy just south of Naples, is actually further east. (One of those things you dont believe until you look at a map like the fact that Reno, Nevada, is west of Los Angeles.) But itll be the farthest inland Ive been in Europe, as well as my first visit to a former communist country.
The topic of my presentation is Rule-following, Praxeology, and Anarchy. Heres an abstract:
The aim of Ludwig Wittgensteins rule-following paradox is to diagnose a seductive error that Wittgenstein sees as underlying a variety of different philosophical mistakes: the implicit assumption of the need for and/or possibility of a self-applying rule. A further implication of Wittgensteins diagnosis is that human action is not reducible either to purely mentalistic or to purely behavioural phenomena.Adios till next week!
If, as I shall argue, Wittgensteins analysis is correct, then, I shall further argue, the rule-following paradox has important implications for two aspects of Austrian theory.
First, Wittgensteins argument sheds light on the relation between economic theory and economic history i.e., between the aprioristic method of praxeology and the interpretive method of thymology, as Ludwig von Mises uses those terms in Theory and History. In particular, it shows that, just as thymological interpretation involves praxeological categories, so the possession of praxeological categories involves thymological experience thus enabling a reconciliation of the superficially opposed insights of Mises Kantian approach, Murray Rothbards Aristotelean approach, and Don Lavoies hermeneutical approach to Austrian methodology.
Second, Wittgensteins argument provides a way of defending the stateless legal order advocated by Rothbard, Lavoie, and others. Critics of free-market anarchism often charge that a stateless society lacks, yet needs, a final arbiter or ultimate authority to resolve conflicts; but what such critics mean by a final arbiter turns out to be yet another version of the self-applying rule that Wittgenstein has shown is neither needed nor possible.