Blogs > Liberty and Power > Virtù, Selfishness, and the Limits to Government

Mar 9, 2006

Virtù, Selfishness, and the Limits to Government




In this post, I discuss Machiavelli's idea of civic virtue, contrasting it with subsequent classical liberal models holding that disparate self-interests are, paradoxically, the engine of social well-being. A vast gulf seems to separate the two notions. Yet where are the appropriate boundaries for self-interest as relates to government, or to the use of force, in a libertarian society? Machiavelli may have something to teach us yet.

I. Virtù and Selfishness. Machiavelli called it virtù: Successful polities, he argued, possessed a sense of public-mindedness that brought their citizens to do what was right for the state even when it contravened their private interests. Sometimes translated as civic virtue, public spirit, or just plain virtue, virtù was Machiavelli's chief explanation for the success and failure of political enterprises from antiquity to the Renaissance. Societies possessing virtù would sacrifice their wealth, their comfort, and even their sons so that good government would continue. And paradoxically, through sacrifice they would usually prosper.

The trouble with virtù, however, was that it was almost intrinsically fleeting. Societies kept their virtù only so long as they resisted the temptation toward softness: While virtù brought strength, strength brought wealth. In turn, wealth brought luxury, vice, and effeminacy. In other words, virtù contained the seeds of its own destruction. For
Machiavelli, history could be explained as an ongoing battle between virtù and decadence. (Yes, there's a painfully obvious gender angle here. I may eventually discuss it in another post.)

Machiavelli shocked his contemporaries in part because his idea of virtù was audaciously pagan: It had little or nothing to do with Christian ideas of virtue, positing that perhaps the best interests of the Church did not always coincide with those of the state. Virtù may have had nothing to do with selfishness, but it had still less to do with Christian humility.

As Bernard Crick put it in his introduction to Machiavelli's Discourses (the relevant portion of which can be read here):


'Civic spirit' is probably the best simple translation—if by 'spirit' one means spirited action, like the arete of the early Greeks -- as in Homer's description of Achilles as being 'a doer of deeds and a speaker of words'; and in Machiavelli's relishing the significance of Achilles' tutor having been a centaur, 'half-beast and half-man'. Lastly, while he often uses the term in a hortatory way -- people should recover their virtù' while there is time, or should not have let it idle away into ozio (indolence or corruption) -- its force is as often empirical. Does a state have virtù among its inhabitants or not? Are there, in a word, citizens? If there are no or too few citizens, one is doomed to personal or princely rule; but if many, then a republic can flourish, and will prove — the by now familiar argument — the stronger form of state. Look around the modern world. It is a reasonably precise criterion. To give one dangerous example. Leave aside the rights and the wrongs of the Arab-Israeli conflict. Is it not obvious that the weakness, for all their numbers and arms, of the Arabs is related to the historical lack and the slow development of a class of citizens -- men who combine individual initiative with collective discipline? And that much of the strength of Israel is related to its citizen culture?

(Two complete asides: My own edition adds the words"as well as to foreign subvention" before the final question mark, which dilutes the argument considerably. I would have left them off. Elsewhere, Crick also makes a howling error about the French Revolution, claiming that universal manhood suffrage was never imagined by the men of 1793; in reality, the French Constitution of 1793 made France the first European polity ever to adopt the measure. But aside from this error, I found Crick's introduction to the Discourses to be one of the most stimulating pieces of writing I have encountered for many
weeks.)

In England, Machiavelli's ideas would later animate many of what are now termed the classical republican thinkers, men like Algernon Sidney and John Milton. Cato's Letters (excerpts here), from which the Cato Institute takes its name, are likewise typical of this strain of republican and proto-libertarian thought.

The classical republicans also exerted a strong influence on the founding of the American republic. When Benjamin Franklin famously declared that the Constitutional Convention had given America"a republic, if you can keep it," the second half of his epigram was a clear reference to the civic virtue that our founders hoped would sustain the American experiment. Many of the Federalist Papers are also informed by an appreciation of how difficult it is to maintain a republic. While present-day Americans may think that liberal democracy is one of the easiest and most natural things in the world, our founders thought it could only be won -- and maintained -- through tremendous sacrifice.

Yet even in the late eighteenth century, an intellectual revolution was already underway, and classical republicanism was on the wane. Inspired by thinkers like Bernard de Mandeville and Adam Smith, those who prized human liberty increasingly declared that neither freedom nor progress demanded very much in the way of civic virtue or self-sacrifice for the good of the polity: Prosperity, good government, and even virtuous individual character might instead arise through the pursuit of fundamentally selfish goals. In his poem"The Fable of the Bees," Mandeville wrote,


Thus every Part was full of Vice,
Yet the whole Mass a Paradice;
Flatter'd in Peace, and fear'd in Wars
They were th'Esteem of Foreigners,
And lavish of their Wealth and Lives,
The Ballance of all other Hives.
Such were the Blessings of that State;
Their Crimes conspired to make 'em Great;
And Vertue, who from Politicks
Had learn'd a Thousand cunning Tricks,
Was, by their happy Influence,
Made Friends with Vice: And ever since
The worst of all the Multitude
Did something for the common Good.

This was the State's Craft, that maintain'd
The Whole, of which each Part complain'd:
This, as in Musick Harmony,
Made Jarrings in the Main agree;
Parties directly opposite
Assist each oth'r, as 'twere for Spight;
And Temp'rance with Sobriety
Serve Drunkenness and Gluttonny.

The Root of evil Avarice,
That damn'd ill-natur'd baneful Vice,
Was Slave to Prodigality,
That Noble Sin; whilst Luxury.
Employ'd a Million of the Poor,
And odious Pride a Million more.

Clearly we are far removed from Machiavelli's understanding of how a republic endures; the intellectual revolution of which Mandeville was part turned on its head one of the key tenets of classical republicanism. Most subsequent classical liberals have idealized commerce and selfishness to almost the same degree that classical republicans vilified them. And while Franklin quipped of having given America a republic, if it could keep it, many of his other writings reveal him have had inordinate difficulties on the question of pride -- which he knew from experience to be a great motivator. Here he discussed his famous list of practical virtues:

My list of virtues contain'd at first but twelve; but a Quaker friend having kindly informed me that I was generally thought proud; that my pride show'd itself frequently in conversation; that I was not content with being in the right when discussing any point, but was overbearing, and rather insolent, of which he convinc'd me by mentioning several instances; I determined endeavouring to cure myself, if I could, of this vice or folly among the rest, and I added Humility to my list giving an extensive meaning to the word.

I cannot boast of much success in acquiring the reality of this virtue, but I had a good deal with regard to the appearance of it... When another asserted something that I thought an error, I deny'd myself the pleasure of contradicting him abruptly, and of showing immediately some absurdity in his proposition; and in answering I began by observing that in certain cases or circumstances his opinion would be right, but in the present case there appear'd or seem'd to me some difference, etc. I soon found the advantage of this change in my manner; the conversations I engag'd in went on more pleasantly. The modest way in which I propos'd my opinions procur'd them a readier reception and less contradiction; I had less mortification when I was found to be in the wrong, and I more easily prevail'd with others to give up their mistakes and join with me when I happened to be in the right.

The influence of Mandeville -- a sometime friend of Franklin's -- is clear: The appearance of virtue may well be enough, and pride may well be the engine that drove all of Franklin's legendary hard work. Franklin seems to demand of himself not Christian virtue, nor even virtù, but a crafty self-interest and a pleasant demeanor.

Especially in the twentieth century, something like Mandeville's position won a decisive victory among libertarians: From Ayn Rand, who extolled the virtue of selfishness, to Friedrich Hayek, who argued that a wide array of helpful social systems arose through amoral and shortsighted transactions, to Robert Nozick, who even offered an invisible hand explanation for the state, civic virtue is nowhere to be found -- except for those rare occasions where it is argued against. (It is easy to see how Rand, who fled the communists, and Hayek, who fled the Nazis, might have come to reject the notion of self-sacrifice for the good of a government, purely for personal reasons. Yet both participated in a trend that had begun well before them and would continue to the present.)

II. The Limits of Government To ensure the properly selfish life, Rand, Hayek, and many others demanded sharp limits on the power of government. Across many different lines of modern libertarian thought, government is conceived as an obstacle to self-fulfillment, understood either as man's proper aim in life or as the creator of most of our other beneficial social attributes. More often than not, government gets in the way because it introduces inauthentic motives, distorts the proper relationships among individuals, and even tempts people toward a worship of the collective at the expense of the self. Broadly speaking, this is the libertarian account of fascism and communism, and it has always seemed to me one of the areas where libertarian political thought rang the truest.

We are to expand the realm of the individual, because -- in Rand's formulation -- the individual, and not society, is the prime mover of the world, or because -- in Hayek's -- we do not understand and cannot possibly understand the complex honeycomb that we all create through the pursuit of our own self-interests. In either case, the prescription is roughly the same.

How, though, are we to achieve our goal? A wide variety of tactics have been suggested, from Objectivism's stress on rationality and proper cultural values as the foundation for a free society -- all the way to the Rothbard Caucus's proposal to dismantle all improper government programs immediately and without regard for consequence.

Each in its own way, the various strains of libertarianism are grappling with the problems of public choice theory, and, in his own way, Machiavelli acknowledged . As Wikipedia explains (I think fairly),


One of the basic claims that obtain from public choice theory is that good government policies in a democracy are an underprovided public good, because of the rational ignorance of the voters. Each voter is faced with an infinitesimally small probability that his vote will change the result of the elections, while gathering the relevant information necessary for a well-informed voting decision requires substantial time and effort. Therefore, the rational decision for each voter is to be generally ignorant of politics and perhaps even abstain from voting. Rational choice theorists claim that this explains the gross ignorance of most citizens in modern democracies as well as low voter turnout.

While the good government tends to be a pure public good for the mass of voters, there exists a plethora of various interest groups that have strong incentives for lobbying the government to implement specific inefficient policies that would benefit them at the expense of the general public. For example, lobbying by the sugar manufacturers might result in an inefficient subsidy for the production of sugar, either direct or by protectionist measures. The costs of such inefficient policy are dispersed over all citizens, and therefore unnoticeable to each individual. On the other hand, the benefits are shared by a very small special interest group, who has very strong incentives to perpetuate the policy by further lobbying. The vast majority of voters will be completely unaware of the whole affair due to the phenomenon of rational ignorance. Therefore, theorists expect that numerous special interests will be able to successfully lobby for various inefficient policies.

Inspired by the inaugural essay at Cato Unbound, James Buchanan's"Three Amendments: Responsibility, Generality, and Natural Liberty," Sandefur has argued that there is no possible way to write a constitution whose text escapes the fundamental problem of public choice in politics. He writes,


At Cato Unbound, Prof. James Buchanan.. recommends amending the United States Constitution to say something like (in Hayek's words)"Congress shall make no law authorizing government to take any discriminatory measures of coercion." He's open to other phrases, but the idea is to enshrine the principle of"generality, which has long been accepted as the central element in the rule of law."

Buchanan believes that we can limit the public choice problem by establishing a constitutional limit on differential benefits, but, as Anthony de Jasay explains in his essay, On Treating Like Cases Alike, reprinted in Justice And Its Surroundings 170 (2002), there is a major problem with this: constitutional rules are subject to the same public choice pressures that influence statutes. As Jasay puts it, interest groups not only" choose legislation that maximizes their gains from politics," they also"learn to choose a constitution that maximizes the scope for such legislation."

...Requiring"generality" doesn't answer the question, therefore, of what sort of laws are general and what are special, because it doesn't explain what variables are to be considered relevant when determining whether one case is like another case. Those variables are potentially infinite, and many have a great deal of plausibility. But once we decide on some, then we have loaded the game and our"general" laws are no longer truly"general" in a meaningful sense.

...You see now why I once referred to this essay as"spooky." It suggests that there is no possible solution to the fundamental problem of politics — no matter how philosophically savvy the people are!

Call it the Goedel's Incompleteness Theorem of limited government: No matter how we set the limits, there will always be people with the proper personal incentives to wish to circumvent them; no matter how we write the rules, there will always be ways of rendering these same rules moot. And if there aren't any such ways, then people, in their infinite turpitude, will invent them. In a flash, we are back at Machiavelli, who demaned a certain public-spiritedness, a certain virtù, as a precondition for liberty. And I daresay that even in an anarcho-capitalist system, the same might well be required: Even granting for the sake of argument that all the rest of anarcho-capitalist theory is right, what, if not some quality or virtue of the people, would prevent an anarcho-capitalism from degenerating into a mere government?

[Crossposted at Positive Liberty.]



comments powered by Disqus

More Comments:


Geoffrey Allan Plauche - 3/12/2006

I just uploaded a revised version of my paper that is different in some important respects. Anyone who downloaded or read it before this might want to get the new version.


Jason Pappas - 3/11/2006

Thanks to both of you for your recommendations. I'm eager to read more on these topics.


Geoffrey Allan Plauche - 3/11/2006

Agreed.

But what of republican virtue in general, which one might term not the mundane sort of patriotism that is generally bandied about today but rather an exalted patriotism, a collectivist virtue involving love of country, public service, and self-sacrifice to the Greater Good of the group? It seems to me that Roman republican virtue is only a particularly disciplined and sanguinary species of this virtue idealized by republican statists.

I'm in agreement with Roderick, and perhaps with you as well, that some degree of virtue is as necessary for a free society as a respect for individual rights - indeed, that some degree of libertarian virtue is necessary for respect for rights. However, it is not only the individual martial virtue of the Romans that I find subversive of true liberty, but the kind of virtue that is republican virtue as well.

I look forward to any comments you may have on my paper. And thanks for including links in yours to several interesting papers I hadn't known about.


Jason T. Kuznicki - 3/10/2006

Thank you for the pointer; I will be sure to read your work and comment on it by e-mail.

In the meantime, I'd just like to note that while some type of individual virtue may be necessary to sustain a libertarian regime, it need not be the same type of individual virtue championed by the Romans. I would be the first to agree that Roman liberty is nothing like the sort of liberty I would prefer.


Geoffrey Allan Plauche - 3/10/2006

Jason,

It is rather interesting that you seem to see republican or civic virtue as a possible necessary foundation of a free society. I have an unfinished working paper on Rome in which I reach the opposite conclusion: that republican virtue is detrimental to the long-term survival of liberty. It can be found here <http://www.veritasnoctis.net/docs/romepaper.pdf>;. In it I may liberal use of Bastiat's excellent observations on Roman virtue and liberty.


Jason T. Kuznicki - 3/10/2006

You're right -- this is a book-length topic, and a lot of what I was doing here was really to clarify (in my own mind) the links among various books I've read.

For more on Machiavelli and how he fits into English republicanism, the indispensible work is J.G.A. Pocock's _The Machiavellian Moment_, though be warned that it is also a very difficult read. You may also want to read Pocock's _Virtue, Commerce, and History_, a collection of essays about Machiavelli, his intellectual world, and many of the questions raised above. The connections to modern libertarian thought are remote, however, and the "work" I did, again in my own mind, was mostly to connect this scholarship on Machiavelli to present-day classical liberal thought.


Jason T. Kuznicki - 3/10/2006

I didn't say I had any answers; these are puzzling questions to me as well.

I do think that among the general public, education about economics, personal freedom, and the like is necessary for any good society to take shape or endure: If enough people lack these understandings, they will be apt to band together and subvert even a relatively good social system.

I'm in the middle of Machiavelli's _Discourses_ now, and I am struck again and again by how he anticipated so many of these issues, especially in the area of public choice theory, even if he was remarkably ignorant about many things that we would now take for granted.

In a sense, his idea of civic virtue is a fairly poor explanation, as it is often the only thing he can use to show how historical actors managed to make the "right" choice for their societies, and to leave aside the temptation to turn the state to their own advantage. In the end, this isn't much of an explanation, but he is at least clear that the problem exists, which is remarkable for his time.

It's still frustrating to me, since, as you point out, "civic virtue" seems to explain so little, but Machiavelli's struggles here do show truly remarkable mind grappling with some very hard questions.

One conspicuous absence from Machiavelli's thought is the idea that social systems usually develop gradually and organically. Although he does provide a fascinating description of how mixed government may have arisen quasi-spontaneously, his emphasis is almost always on individual actors and the deliberate designs that they created: He seems inevitably to assume that any workable social system must always have had a single designer. I may make this the subject of a future post as I continue to read, slowly and carefully, through the _Discourses_.

As I pointed out, Smith, Mandeville and their heirs argued in favor of spontaneous orders in one sense or another -- yet it may well be that their argument only goes so far, and that spontaneous systems only make up _some_ of the distance between where we are and the ideal. Perhaps maintaining them also takes a certain personal virtue. That's the question I'm posing here, and I don't yet have an answer to it.


Jason T. Kuznicki - 3/10/2006

I stand corrected.


Robert Higgs - 3/9/2006

Your refer to "Hayek, who fled the Nazis." Well, not exactly. Hayek went to live in London, to teach at the LSE, in the fall of 1931, well before the Nazis took over in his native Austria. Later, it's true, he certainly could not have returned safely to Austria, after the Nazis really had taken over. There's no doubt, however, that Hayek abhorred the Nazis and wrote many of his works, including The Road to Serfdom, with the Nazis foremost in his mind.


Jason Pappas - 3/9/2006

You’re raising the important issue; one that I often believe gets shortchanged in libertarian discussions. Recently, as I re-read Bailyn’s classic, “The Ideological Origins of the American Revolution,” I was taken with the emphasis of classical virtue within the libertarian/individualist context. I comment on it here.

Of course, the Greeks didn’t contrast virtue/excellence/flourishing with selfishness but with hedonism. Thus, the "virtue vs. selfishness distinction," so common today, groups behavior differently from the more healthy and virile notion of virtue as a capacity to tackle life’s challenges and be a worthy member of a civilized order.

I’d like to suggest that Rand falls into the Hellenic paradigm by holding that self-interested be rational, principled, and long-range. She avoids hedonism, the indulgence of given desires, in lieu of a cultivation of character in accord to a rational standard. She divides behavior differently by subsuming investment (the postponement of gratification) into egoism instead of see it as part of self-sacrifice (which also includes utter purposeless suffering.)

Of course, this is going beyond your article and I didn’t mean to imply that you might disagree with this. I merely wanted to suggest that you’ve presented a book-length topic in a short article. One can take any paragraph and expand it to a chapter by making further distinctions, comparisons, re-groupings, etc. Perhaps there is a book out there that deals with this topic. Can anyone recommend one? (If it’s your book, I’ll most likely buy a copy!)


Craig J. Bolton - 3/9/2006

A generally excellent discussion.

However, one thing I did not see, that has always bothered me in these sorts of discussions, is "whose virtue." If we are not dealing with a totalitarian society, then the "who" is not just the Great Leader or the Party. But who is it?

Are all of our "average Joes" to become masters of the "fundamentals" of political and economic theory as participatory democrats? If not, who and how wide must this "virtue" be?

And, if the virtue need not be universal then perhaps a Mandevillian move might not be made at this point. If "self-sacrificing" "virtue" is really required of some "ruling class" less than the adult voting population, then shouldn't that ruling class be "paid off" in some currency other than enhanced wealth and income? Isn't this what the late 18th Century emphasis on "fame" and "reputation" was about? Isn't that why Washington refused the Crown and always managed to devise matters so that he never appeared to be "ambitious?"

And if a lust for "fame" is desirable, then maybe "deference" and "admiration," also have a coordinate role in maintaining the society?

But there's that dilema again, since such "deference" and "admiration" often attach to the office and not to the particular traits of the person holding the office - "due deference" soon becomes just slavish obedience and..... around and around we go.....